There is always a risk of this sort of thing of getting sidetracked by asking “who are these ‘rationalists’ anyway?” or “what count as ‘conservative’ ideas?”. Rather than engage in any definitional throat-clearing, I will simply point you towards a couple of examples and I hope you will see what I'm getting at.
– Example 1: this, from me, about how (among other things) very clever modern rationalists have worked out that it's a good idea to treat manioc according to the traditions of your ancestors even though you don't know why. One theme this illustrates is epistemic humility, in particular “Chesterton's Fence”, a little argument derived from Chesterton and beloved by rationalists to the effect that until you understand the real purpose of a feature of life, you have no business getting rid of it.
– Example 2: this, also from me, picking up on how very clever modern Effective Altruists have carefully worked out a number of bits of common sense, e.g., that charity begins at home and that sometimes foreign aid money gets siphoned off by the bad guys. One theme that emerges from that thread is that having good institutions is a Good Thing.
I
think it’s pretty obvious that thinking that Chesterton’s Fence is valuable
reasoning is pretty conservative. For one thing, Chesterton himself was that
way inclined. For another, the idea that you shouldn’t just ditch old-fashioned
things just because they seem useless is almost a parody of conservative
thinking.
The more interesting case is institutions. McLaughlin pointed out that there are perfectly good liberal, Hayekian reasons for supporting institutions, and he directed me to an interesting piece he wrote about (among other things) how different liberal traditions think about the threats or values that institutions present or protect.
I
would recommend that you read McLaughlin’s piece. It’s interesting in its own
right. Also, you’ll be able to judge whether I’m misrepresenting the thrust of
his argument. But whether you have read it or not, here goes my reasoning for
why what the rationalist thinks about institutions is properly to be described
as “conservative” rather than “liberal”.
Liberalism
is famously a broad church. But if there is a core sense to liberalism – a sense
in which people on the Left can ultimately be pinned down as being liberals
rather than, say, socialists, or people on the Right can be pinned down as
being liberals rather than, say, conservatives – it must surely be something to
do with individual liberty. (Or freedom, or political liberty, or autonomy, or
...) At root, it’s all about people (in some sense of the word ‘people’)
getting to exercise personal choice (some more or less informed and more or
less restrained kind of choice) about the things that matter to them and the
polities to which they belong.
That
means that – ultimately, at some point, when the chips are down – the liberal
has to say that institutions are justified by what they do for individual
freedom. So, for example, to return to McLaughlin’s piece, we see that it might
be said that “[intermediate institutions, e.g. churches] are themselves the
site of freedom” or that “mediaeval cities [i.e., another set of
institutions] were often quite literally founded on a contract, and that their
offer of significant individual freedom to their citizens was the basis of the
contractarian understanding of liberty”, and that that kind of thinking is
why these institutions are Good Things.
The
first example of an institution that came to my mind when I was thinking about
this issue was the National Trust. I think it’s a good example. The National
Trust is definitely a political thing: it’s the subject of several acts of
Parliament, it makes statements about matters of public importance (e.g. the
environment) and it’s forever in the news for being too “woke” or not “woke”
enough.
So
why does the liberal think that the National Trust is a Good Thing (if indeed
s/he thinks it is)? The answer will be along the lines of “the National Trust
is a way for people to express themselves and live life fully by freely
participating together in an activity in which they have chosen to take part
and collaborate”.
More generally, if asked “what is this (good) institution good for?” or even “what
is it for?”, the liberal will have to give the answer “freedom”.
Now of course, conservatives don’t say anything like that. If asked “what is
this institution good for?” (or “what is it for?”) they will answer in terms
referable to the institution’s own goals, e.g., “the purpose of the National
Trust – the good of the National Trust – is to preserve nice old
buildings; that’s what it’s for” (or “what it’s good for”). The conservative
values the institution in itself, not merely as a means towards an
end of political freedom.
So
far, so familiar. But what do rationalists say?
Broadly
speaking, rationalists have some kind of utilitarian or at least
consequentialist outlook on life, which at first sight seems far removed from
conservative modes of thinking. However, let’s investigate a little further.
Rationalists are discovering (see my example 2 above) that the best way of
delivering some desired outcome is to build a solid institution with a healthy
culture that will scale up, perpetuate itself, learn from its mistakes, be
resilient to chancers, fraudsters and failure etc etc. It seems to me that that
means that when we ask, “what is this (good) institution good for?” or “what is
it for?”, the answer given by rationalists will be phrased in terms of the
desired goal of the institution.
Let’s
return to the National Trust. If we suppose that rationalists were to discover
that the preservation of nice old buildings was something that made people much
happier, or improved life outcomes in some measurable way – and, let’s face it,
that’s exactly the sort of thing they might well discover – then they would end
up saying, for example, “the purpose of the National Trust – the good of the
National Trust – is to preserve nice old buildings; that’s what it’s for” (or “what
it’s good for”). The rationalist has therefore arrived at exactly the same
destination as the conservative.
Of
course, the rationalist and the conservative may head off in different
directions afterwards. If asked “why should we preserve nice old buildings?”
then the rationalist might point to studies showing that people who visit nice
old buildings have better mental health or are more productive, while the
conservative might just say “because they are nice and old and part of our
shared history”. I am not saying that their ultimate values are aligned. But I
do say that what we see is a common test for what makes an institution
valuable.
I
think the point is even clearer if we consider how an institution might fail.
What would count as the failure of the National Trust?
The
liberal will say that the National Trust will have failed – will have become a
Bad Thing – if, say it becomes so over-bearing of its membership’s day to day
lives that their freedom is infringed, or if it exercises so much power over
the wider polity that conservation concerns crowd out freedom of association
more generally.
Now
of course any sane person would be rather worried by a National Trust that
turned into a cult or a conspiracy against the public. But those are weird
answers to the question. Both the conservative and the rationalist would surely
say that the most obvious way for the National Trust to fail is by failing to
do what it’s meant to do, i.e. preserve nice old buildings. Maybe the
conservative is more annoyed if it fails by spending money on spreading “woke
nonsense” while the rationalist is more annoyed if it fails by spending money
on ineffective preservation techniques. But there’s not a lot in it: both sets
of people are annoyed by both kinds of failure.
What
I find harder to understand is why the liberal could object to the National
Trust failing in that way. If the membership are sufficiently involved in the
decision making (i.e. freedom internal to the National Trust is
protected/enhanced) and wider society is still free and vibrant (i.e. freedom
external to the National Trust is protected/enhanced), then what’s the problem?
There is no problem for the liberal (qua liberal anyway).
Of
course, it’s open to the liberal to say that that’s no black mark against
liberalism. There are political goods and there are other goods, and the
liberal need have no position on whether the National Trust is doing a good
job, just as the liberal need have no position on whether the manager of the
England football team is doing a good job.
But
I don’t find that a terribly convincing answer. I started by giving the
National Trust as an example of a political organisation, in the broadest
sense, and I stand by that. Many things that the National Trust does are
apolitical, granted, but it also plays a recognisable role in the life of the
nation; it is surely a shortcoming in your political theory if you can’t
evaluate whether the National Trust is doing its job properly or not.
Standing
back from rationalists and the National Trust, I think there’s a broader point.
Conservatism is perhaps a set of attitudes and prejudices more than it is an
intellectual position. But (perhaps surprisingly) it is quite good at finding
intellectual supports for those attitudes and prejudices.
Hayekian
thought is a good example: his ideas about decentralised information and free
markets provided support for the instinctive love of private property and
dislike of socialism that were a feature of mid-twentieth century conservatism.
More recently, those elements of liberal thought that emphasise freedom of
speech have become “right-coded”, providing intellectual cover for
conservatives’ instinctive dislike of the Islamic blasphemy laws and various
forms of politically correct speech. We are, I think, seeing many of those
feminists and post-feminists who place particular emphasis on the biological
nature – and inherent biological vulnerabilities – of women providing arguments
that right-wingers are happy with.
None
of that is to say that all of those people are conservative (or, even less,
vote Conservative), simply that where their concerns and arguments echo those
of genuine conservatives, the magpie-like minds of right are happy to them pick
up and (culturally) appropriate them.
The
rationalists are a good new source of sustenance for conservative thinking,
just as the feminists and liberals were before them. I shouldn’t let the topic
rest without noting that there are a number of rather unpleasant alternative
sources of new ideas and sustenance, but I will leave that as a topic for
another day.
No comments:
Post a Comment